Iain D. Thomson: Heidegger on Technology’s Danger and Promise in the Age of AI

Heidegger on Technology’s Danger and Promise in the Age of AI Book Cover Heidegger on Technology’s Danger and Promise in the Age of AI
Elements in the Philosophy of Martin Heidegger
Iain D. Thomson
Cambridge University Press
Paperback
74

Reviewed by: Giorgi Vachnadze

 

“How exactly is technology transforming us and our worlds, and what (if anything) can and should we do about it?” This is the opening question in Thomson’s (2025) book: Heidegger on Technology’s Danger and Promise in the Age of AI. No doubt a very much needed and anticipated reflection on how the original ideas in, for instance, the Question Concerning Technology[1] would react with the contemporary discourse on Artificial Intelligence. No less importantly, Thomson combines the algorithmic anxieties of our age with fears concerning things that have been lurking in our globalized (inter)cultural unconscious throughout the 20th and 21st centuries: nuclear technology, genome engineering and synthetic biology. As we enter the new stage of the Anthropocene[2] with Utopian promises and Dystopian nightmares, Thomson’s work could give us a compact handbook to reanimate the Heideggerian call to start thinking and (therefore) acting in new ways through the use and abuse of technological artefacts.  

Thomson’s approach is both historical and philosophical, tracing the trajectory of Heidegger’s thoughts on technology while contextualizing them within modern advancements. The exploration of Gestell (enframing) as the operative mode of revealing that structures human perception of reality is central, as AI is situated within the larger continuum of destructive, panopticonic (Foucault, 1995) and subjectivating (Foucault, 2008) technological “advancements”[3]. Thomson addresses Heidegger’s notion of Gelassenheit (releasement) as a potential means of cultivating a more reflective, in some ways poetic engagement with technology, succumbing neither to its charms, nor rejecting it outright.

The review will outline Thomson’s key arguments, exploring how he applies Heidegger’s ideas to AI and other technological concerns of the present. We will explore the book’s central themes, discuss the main insights, and consider its broader relevance. By revisiting Heidegger in this context, Thomson invites us to reassess the ways in which technology not only transforms the world but also reshapes the very conditions of human thought and action.

Technology is a provocation to philosophical thought. Precisely in so far as it is a challenge to thinking itself. Technological thinking threatens to make thinking redundant by rendering it reductively computational. Philosophy is thereby cornered; if thinking is calculation, then philosophy as the art of thinking becomes obsolete – replaceable. If the simulacrum of thought (Baudrillard, 1994) becomes thought itself, then technological thinking would easily automate the philosopher’s job. But the real concern (Sorge) here is what happens to thinking as such in a technological age. And how can philosophers still think something that is relevant, new and most importantly; irreducible to algorithmic thinking (Vachnadze, 2024a 2024b) or “mere” calculation? Among many other questions, Thomson explores how Heidegger could help us step outside the confines of our episteme (Foucault, 2005) and think the thought of the Outside (Debnar, 2017) through technology.

In the chapter: From Atomic Weapons to Genetic Engineering and Artificial Intelligence the author takes on a monumental task of tracing the ontological shifts induced by three of the most consequential technological advances of the modern era. Thomson’s discussion of nuclear technology is one of the chapter’s strongest sections. Thomson frames the nuclear age not just as a political and military development, but as an ontological rupture—an epochal shift in how humanity relates to power in so far as it relates so to itself through the fundamental ontological structure of Dasein – anxiety. Major global catastrophes; more so their potential eruption, occupies a fascinating ontological space vis-a-vis the human psyche. The general sense of an impending doom, with no clear indication of which direction the destruction will come from, bears a strong resemblance, acting as pretext almost to the fundamental anxiety that structures human experience. What under different circumstances would have been “pure” anxiety, just the existential condition of being-in-the-world for Dasein, is now triggered by a material, yet no less ethereal threat of world-annihilation. But this time no longer only in the metaphysical, but in the literal sense as well.

Modern thought and its obsession with enframing (Gestell), an obsessive attempt to measure, optimize and calculate every aspect of the world, seems to find a kind of culmination with generative AI and Natural Language Processing software. ChatGPT tends to – or effectively does – turn thinking itself into a standing reserve. If we assume Cartesian dualism (another symptom of modern thinking), it seems then that genetic engineering would be enframing the body, whereas Artificial Intelligence would enframe the mind (through the enframing of language). Leading consequently to a total Neoliberal bio-commodification and the splitting up of the human lifeworld (Husserl, 1970). Nothing short of capitalist eugenics.

Returning to Thomson’s work; the author takes multiple moments to expose the distortions and ideological manipulations of both the utopian and fatalistic narratives around AI that have now reached eschatological dimensions (Vachnadze, 2024c). Heidegger offers a fruitful middle ground that avoids the pitfalls of both corporate hype and nihilist doom. In chapter 3 Thomson elaborates on Heidegger’s infamous diagnosis of the cybernetic age. The notion that the essence of technology – which strictly speaking is not an “essence” in the classical sense of a fixed abstract Platonic core, but more something along the lines of a process-philosophical understanding of the term – is something rather indeterminate. It is, one could say, an essence of becoming technological, a style of being. More importantly, as Thomson notes, quoting Heidegger, the essence of technology is “nothing technological” (2025). That is, the essence of technology is quite different from its material manifestation in the form of various concrete apparatuses and tools. It is thereby neither abstract nor empirical. It is a kind of thinking, a mode of “going about” in the world that precedes and establishes the conditions of possibility for technology. Thereby Thomson, via Heidegger, offers an insightful exposition of the contemporary episteme. In short, the essence of technology is precisely what we mentioned earlier: An enframing of nature that makes the world into a standing reserve ready to be exploited, extracted and used. One could go as far as to say that the essence of technology is a kind of ethical attitude, or more importantly perhaps, an unethical attitude or concern that Dasein exhibits toward the world, toward other Daseins, and toward itself.

Thomson argues that modernity consists of two distinct epochs continuous with one another: early modern subjectivism and late-modern enframing. Together they constitute the modern subject establishing Dasein’s fundamental concern with being and technology. The guiding question here is whether Heidegger’s philosophy allows for a postmodern alternative beyond the nihilism of late-modern technological enframing. Each epoch, Thomson continues, is temporarily stabilized through a unique ontotheology – a dual structure that anchors both an inner, foundational understanding of being (ontology) and an external, overarching framework that grants meaning to existence (theology). Throughout Western history, these ontotheological foundations have given successive epochs their coherence.

Late modernity marks a radical departure from the historical ontotheological pattern. The late-modern age is thoroughly Nietzschean. Dominated by the “metaphysics” of will to power and eternal recurrence. Here the Western tradition reaches an impasse: rather than anchoring reality to a stable ontotheological foundation, the contemporary episteme dissolves and gives way to a groundless, ceaseless flux of mere competing forces. As a result, modernity’s attempt to achieve mastery over being through rationality, science, and technology culminates in a paradox: Dasein that once sought control over reality becomes itself reduced to an object, stripped of all metaphysical or phenomenological privilege. Marking the transition from modern subjectivism to late-modern enframing[4].

This paves the way for a post-modern Heideggerian attempt to make a clearing for thought that could potentially escape both the constraining dispositif of computational reductionism as well as the threat of complete chaotic dissolution into non-sense. “When a metaphysics is truly “great” (in Heidegger’s terms), it quietly spreads a new “understanding of being” far and wide until it has settled into taken-for-granted common sense (Thomson, 2025). Ontotheology, far from a whimsical flight of the philosophical imagination, is what provides the most basic foundations for our understanding of the world. Despite being foundational, it is nonetheless subject to change, as each epoch reflects on its own conditions of existence quite differently. Thomson traces the emergence of subjectivism in early modernity, focusing on the Cartesian and Kantian traditions. Cartesianism establishes human cognition as the foundation of certainty, Kant further develops this framework and makes the rational subject the cornerstone of ethics, politics, and aesthetics. Subjectivism, Thomson argues, is Heidegger’s term for the modern drive to establish mastery over the totality of what-is – a metaphysical project that underlies the scientific and technological developments of the modern age.

At the same time Heidegger explains how this framework mischaracterizes human experience by treating the world as a collection of objects external to the subject, rather than an integrated network of beings. The subject, in the quest to master the world, inadvertently sets the stage for her own self-objectification. As modernity progresses, subjectivism increasingly loses its metaphysical coherence, giving way to the late-modern epoch of enframing. Enframing is a self-overcoming of subjectivism. The subject-object dichotomy is no longer viable. The will to mastery becomes an endless process of optimization, in which the subject loses its ontological distinctiveness and becomes indistinguishable from the technological systems it once used to steer.

The danger of enframing, and danger is an important component here, also creates the possibilities of thinking the Outside of the given epistemic formation. The very forces that threaten to enclose human existence within technological enframing might also contain the potential for an alternative mode of (thinking) being. The possibility for a post-metaphysical alternative that does not attempt to establish a new ontotheology but seeks rather to twist free (verwinden) from technological enframing would involve shifting from a mode of instrumental rationality toward one of meditative thinking (Besinnung), where being is encountered as something that both informs and exceeds conceptualization. Thomson argues that the postmodern revolution can already be traced through the works of figures like Hölderlin, Van Gogh, and Nietzsche. “Heidegger’s postmodern revolution began over two centuries ago” (Thomson, 2025). The dispersed and polysemic thinking offered by these and similar writers/artists; a thinking of multiplicities perhaps, contain insights that could help resist nihilistic-technological enframing.

The initial question returns in new and altered form as we reach the final culminating chapter: Thinking a Free Relation to Technology, or: Technology and the Other (Postmodern) Beginning. What in the beginning was posed as “How exactly is technology transforming us and our worlds, and what (if anything) can and should we do about it?” has now become: “How do we move beyond the nihilistic tendencies of late-modern enframing and into a genuinely free relation to technology?” Thomson weaves previous discussions on technology, metaphysics, and postmodernity together into a coherent Heideggerian response to the technological age.

Our relationship with technology has to be untangled or unframed from its original reductive-computational form not through reactionary rejection, but through a postmodern attunement to being. The phenomenological capacities of technology need to be reactivated in order to make an alternative clearing in Dasein’s relationship with the various tools at its disposal. This implies first seeing; noticing the said alternative potential of deterritorializing artifacts as immanent to technological becoming, and consequently – making use of this potential in a creative way. An event that would see technology as a site of ontological disclosure rather than a device for turning beings into standing reserves of energy is what Heidegger terms Gelassenheit (releasement or “letting be”). Gelassenheit entails the bracketing of the exploitative attitude of enframing by letting beings be and allow beings to reveal themselves differently; on their own terms. A fundamental change of aspect (Wittgenstein, 1953) where we cultivate an open and thoughtful engagement with technology, employing artefacts in new and meaningful ways while rejecting the optimization imperative. Heidegger offers us a techno-political aesthetics of difference.

The optimization imperative is Neoliberal through and through; the reduction of all human activity to the extractive logic of cost/benefit analysis. We have seen the disastrous effects of technological enframing in every institutional domain throughout the world: labor, education, sexuality, jurisdiction etc. Teachers still see AI as an educational problem, rather than the symptom of making students into a standing reserve of labor and profit. The widespread use of AI in and outside the classroom is symptomatic of the optimization crisis. When students view learning as an obstacle between them and the labor market; as a tool of improving one’s credentials for employment rather than a transformative process, the use of AI to generate essays or answer exam questions, far from an ethical lapse or instance of academic misconduct, is rather an entirely logical response to a system structured around efficiency and productivity rather than meaning. A direct consequence of technological enframing.

Thomson’s meticulous engagement with Heidegger’s philosophy reveals a profound tension between the promise and peril of technology. At its core, Heidegger’s critique of enframing is not a reactionary rejection of technological progress but rather a diagnostic tool for understanding the historical shift in our relationship to being. This shift, as Thomson convincingly argues, has now reached a critical point with the emergence of artificial intelligence. As contemporary AI systems increasingly dictate the parameters of knowledge production, human creativity and thought risk being reduced to mere instrumental functions, evaluated through the capitalist diagram of efficiency and calculability. To repeat; however, the essence of technology is nothing technological – meaning that any escape from its grasp cannot be found in a simple reversal but in a transformation of our mode of thinking itself. Motion without movement.

Thomson’s analysis of late-modern enframing shows how AI, genetic engineering, and nuclear technology represent powerful forces that restructure the conditions of human existence. The danger of technological enframing is twofold: It positions human beings as mere objects within the Bestand (standing reserve), reducing all things – including thinking – to a matter of managing resources; and it obscures the possibility for an alternative mode of being, foreclosing Dasein’s imaginative and existential destiny. Gelassenheit opens up a path to the Outside – a way of inhabiting technology that neither facilitates the production of a Homo-Oeconomicus (Foucault, 2008)  nor retreats into the helpless nostalgia of a pre-technological age. In order to ‘let beings be’ one would require a form of thinking that resists the impulse to master and control, cultivating an openness to the unfolding of being in its plurality.

The implications of this stance are far-reaching. If modernity’s drive for mastery has led to an epoch of nihilistic enframing, then our task is not to overcome technology in the traditional sense but to reorient our relationship to it. Thomson’s invocation of Hölderlin, Van Gogh, and Nietzsche suggests that art and philosophy provide crucial sites of resistance – spaces for the emergence of alternative modes of world-disclosure. This is particularly relevant for recent developments in AI, where the optimization imperative has all but stripped language of its poetic function, making a standing reserve out of thought and all creative human activities through reductive computationalism. Can we re-infuse technology with a poetics of being? More so, can we achieve this with AI and not in spite of it?

The crisis of technological enframing is, once again, also an opportunity: “… where there is danger some salvation grows there too”  (Hölderlin, 2018). An opportunity for a philosophico-poetic clearing where philosophy can reclaim its role as a site of genuine thinking rather than mere calculation. A difficult undertaking. The Neoliberal structure of global capitalism is deeply invested in technological enframing, ensuring that resistance to optimization is met with skepticism, hostility and recently – open fascism. One must bear in mind, once again, that the ontotheological structures of our epochal thinking are not fixed; they are subject to transformations – ruptures, which those tasked with the work of thinking must uncover. We are indeed on the cusp of another major shift – an epochal flight that may only become legible in hindsight. Let us hope that the philosopher does not arrive too late.

Ultimately, the task of philosophy in the age of AI is not to offer prescriptive solutions but to cultivate a different attunement to the world. Heidegger’s concept of Besinnung, meditative thinking, offers a potential path forward – a way of engaging with technology that does not seek to dominate but rather to listen, to dwell, to allow beings to disclose themselves on their own terms, according to their unique internal logic. This is not a call for passivity but for a radical form of engagement – one that refuses the terms of technological enframing and seeks out new modes of relationality. In this sense, Thomson’s work is in many ways a call to reanimate our mode of being and to make it genuinely conducive to an ethical and political metamorphosis.

The book’s final provocation, whether a free relation to technology is still possible, remains aptly and intentionally open-ended. Following the path-marks laid down by Heidegger, one should bear in mind that every attempt to resolve the problem in advance would throw us back into the mode of enframing, leading to a foreclosure of the very openness that allows for genuine thinking. Thomson leaves us with anxiety –  the future of technology is, as it should be, undecided. The forces of enframing are what constitute power today; and thought must resist by twisting itself free from the algorithm. Whether we succeed in doing so remains contingent on our willingness to embrace the challenge that Heidegger and Thomson set before us: to think, in a world increasingly governed by calculation. What could it mean to stubbornly resist and philosophize today?

 

Bibliography:

Baudrillard, J. (1994). Simulacra and Simulation. Translated by S. Glaser. University of Michigan Press

Davies, J. (2016). The birth of the Anthropocene. University of California Press.

Debnar, M. (2017). Michel Foucault on Transgression and The Thought of Outside. European Journal of Science and Theology13(1), 59-67.

Ellis, E. C. (2018). The Anthropocene: A very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.

Foucault, M. (2005). The order of things. Routledge.

Foucault, M. (2008). The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978-1979 (G. Burchell, Trans.). Palgrave Macmillan.

Foucault, M. (1995). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (A. Sheridan, Trans.). Vintage Books. 

Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology, and other essays. New York: Garland Pub.

Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (D. Carr, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.

Hölderlin, F. (2018). Selected Poetry. Bloodaxe Books.

Lewis, S. L., & Maslin, M. A. (2018). The human planet: How we created the Anthropocene. Yale University Press.

Thomson, I. D. (2025). Heidegger on Technology’s Danger and Promise in the Age of AI. Cambridge University Press.

Vachnadze, G. (2024a, October 17). Cybernetic discourse analysis: “Mother was an AI”. Blue Labyrinths.

Vachnadze, G. (2024b). The incomputability of calculation: Wittgenstein, Turing, and the question of artificial intelligence. Newsletter on the Results of Scholarly Work in Sociology, Criminology, Philosophy and Political Science, 5(1). https://doi.org/10.61439/URSA3237

Vachnadze, G. (2024c). Christian Eschatology of Artificial Intelligence: Pastoral Technologies of Cybernetic Flesh. Becoming.

Wittgenstein, L., & Anscombe, G. E. M. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Basil Blackwell.


[1]  Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology, and other essays. New York: Garland Pub.

[2]  See; Ellis, E. C. (2018), Davies, J. (2016), Lewis, S. L., & Maslin, M. A. (2018).

[3]   Throughout the review I make several connections with Foucault’s work. These connections are my own, Thomson does not make these connections and he does not use Foucault’s texts in his work.

[4]      The two together define Modernity proper.

Frank Schalow: Heidegger’s Ecological Turn






Heidegger’s Ecological Turn: Community and Practice for Future Generations Book Cover




Heidegger’s Ecological Turn: Community and Practice for Future Generations




Routledge Studies in Twentieth-Century Philosophy





Frank Schalow





Routledge




2021




Hardback GBP £120.00




218

Reviewed by: Davide Pilotto (Sorbonne Université – Università del Salento)

The aim of Frank Schalow’s book is to offer a valid alternative to all those political readings of Martin Heidegger that, from Farías (1989) to Faye (2009), from Trawny-Mitchell (2017) to Di Cesare (2018), focus their analysis on the relationship of the author of Sein und Zeit to Nazism or, more recently, on the disruptive impact of the Black Notebooks on Heidegger’s Denkweg. “Yes, Heidegger was a Nazi, not a very important Nazi, just an ordinary one, a provincial petit-bourgeois Nazi”, wrote Alain Badiou, adding however that, “Yes, Heidegger is unquestionably one of the most important philosophers of the twentieth century” (Badiou-Cassin, 2014: 14). Schalow’s work thus seems to adhere to such a thesis, explicitly aiming to open up a new path of thought that attempts to draw on Heideggerian conceptual tools without necessarily running into the outcomes mentioned above. The author’s aim, made clear since the preface, is in fact to “elicit new pathways of thinking that begin to reappear from the shadows of the most poignant criticisms,” using Heideggerian writings “as harboring untapped possibilities for future interpretation” (Schalow, 2022: IX).

Schalow is aware of how his work – and perhaps this is one of its merits – goes against the current with respect to his contemporaries. In a framework in which “most of the scholarly terrain is overgrown with numerous books, which proceed from the same premise of condemnation and foreclose other attempts to re-open what remains ‘unthought’” (Schalow, 2022: 10), he tries in full awareness to open the way to a different operation. Going against the tide of the “vitriolic climate” (Schalow, 2022: 1) in which current Heideggerian studies move, the question, a direct consequence of Badiou’s remark just mentioned, is therefore the following: “How do we stand towards Heidegger’s thinking?” (Schalow, 2022: 1). Can Heideggerian thought still have something to give us? The answer, for the author, is positive: “We cannot preclude the possibility of appropriating Heidegger’s texts in a positive way, in order to elicit insights that withdraw within the subterranean recesses of what is ‘unsaid’ and ‘unthought’” (Schalow, 2022: 6-7).

A necessary consequence of this perspective is the awareness that Schalow’s work proposes itself as an original interpretation of Heideggerian work, explicitly taking on what is “an unconventional way to ‘read’ Heidegger” (Schalow 2022: 7). Drawing on multiple places in his Denkweg, in a theoretical operation that denotes an excellent command of the author, his complexity and his traditional periodizations, Schalow establishes, over the course of five chapters, a reinterpretation of how Heideggerian work can provide the conceptual tools for the development of a new, non-anthropocentric ethics that, by leveraging the notions of dwelling and stewardship, gives rise to a new conception of the political that can cope with the current environmental crisis. Defining the question of the political as “the open-ended question of the origin of law, to its enactment as a measure rooted in the ethos (of dwelling) and the re-inscribing of a language to address the elements of the polis according to formally indicative concepts which underscore our capacity to be free (e.g., by ‘letting-be’), albeit as finite human beings” (Schalow, 2022: X), the author, analyzing Heidegger’s work, wonders whether this does not offer the theoretical tools necessary to answer the following question: “Is it possible to create a space for the polis, which through our capacity to dwell (on the earth) engenders openness outside the dominant paradigm of technocratic rule?” (Schalow, 2022: 2). Beginning with some insights we find in Heidegger’s Letter on “Humanism”, we read that “thinking builds upon the house of Being, the house in which the jointure of Being, in its destinal unfolding, enjoins the essence of the human being to dwell in the truth of Being”, and that, for this reason, “this dwelling is the essence of ‘being-in-the-world’” (Heidegger, 1998: 272). Schalow intends to follow up on Heideggerian statements such as the thesis that “nómos is not only law but more originally the assignment contained in the dispensation of Being”, and consequently “only the assignment is capable of dispatching man into Being”, in the conviction that “more essential than instituting rules is that human beings find the way to their abode in the truth of Being” (Heidegger, 1998: 274). If Heidegger writes that “one day we will, by thinking the essence of Being in a way appropriate to its matter, more readily be able to think what ‘house’ and ‘dwelling’ are” (Heidegger, 1998; 272), Schalow intends to pursue this suggestion. On this bases, he illustrates how “the development of a community must be forged at the juncture between the human and the non-human” (Schalow, 2022: XI), giving rise to a socio-biotic community such as to respond positively to the challenge to which we are called by today’s environmental crisis. The intent, very concrete, is to outline the tracks of “a new nexus of political engagement”, to allow that “the fissure of Heidegger’s thinking (of being) opens the ‘other’ side of praxis” (Schalow, 2022: XIII). The purpose of Schalow’s work thus goes in a pragmatic direction, towards the delineation of a praxis that results in the necessary redefinition of our relationship with the world – in other words, “are we to continue using and exploiting the earth only as a resource, or are we to safeguard the earth as a place of dwelling?” (Schalow, 2022: 5).

It is clearly a matter, as already remarked, of taking Heidegger beyond his limits. It is evident, first of all, as Schalow himself acknowledges, that “his [Heidegger’s] understanding of the political remains limited” (Schalow, 2022: XII), just as it is trivially obvious that “Heidegger did not address specifically ‘climate change’, the ‘greenhouse effect’, ‘global warming’, and the ruptures in the ecosystem from which the virus (or other pathogens) of pandemics may arise” (Schalow, 2022: XII). The intent, however, is precisely to focus on das Ungedachte, on the unthought of Heideggerian thought, thus amplifying some elements that, starting from the aforementioned passages of the Letter on “Humanism”, allow Schalow to argue that, “put simply, in the overturning and subversion of anthropocentricism, we see the beginnings of what we today would call an ‘ecological turn’” (Schalow, 2022: XII).

The first chapter (Seeking New Guidelines for Interpretation, pp. 12-39) serves as a necessary methodological premise to justify the reappropriation of Martin Heidegger’s thought for the purposes previously indicated. Deepening the dialogue with Kant around which the 1928 course entitled Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics is centered, Schalow, moving from the metontology that here arises, outlines a “new topography” from which to question the political without slipping into that “‘monological reductionism’ that falsely equates his philosophy with Nazi ideology” (Schalow, 2022: 13-14). Heidegger, through “his ‘destruction’ of Kant” (Schalow, 2022: 21), arrives at “unraveling the presuppositions on which the metaphysical tradition rests”, presuppositions that, “beginning with the static conception of being as permanent presence, lay the sediments of tradition, which erects rigid metaphysical dichotomies”, thus laying the foundations for “the attempt to undo each of these metaphysical dualisms” (Schalow, 2022: 18). The Kantian dichotomy between freedom and nature, in particular, is subverted by Heidegger through our connection to the earth, with the author of Sein und Zeit explicitly writing that “the problem of freedom arises from and as the problem of world” (Heidegger, 2002: 145), allowing Schalow to express the crux of the matter by arguing that “Heidegger relocates the origin of freedom in Dasein’s way of belonging to and reciprocal responsiveness to being” (Schalow, 2022: 24). What emerges is our role, an affinity with the ecological framework in the guise of “earthbound creatures”, as Schalow points out, referring to Hannah Arendt (Arendt, 1992: 27). Cartesian dualism is overturned through the reference to our belonging to the earth, in turn made possible by the changed conceptual framework within which, instead of the dichotomy between subject and object, Heidegger replaces the notion of Dasein with its in-der-Welt-sein. Human freedom comes then to make its own deeper roots, anchoring itself directly in Being and in its relationship with Being and giving rise to the centrality of the notion of ‘responsiveness’, which Schalow defines as “the fostering of a reciprocal relationship with what is radically other, as conferred by being, rather than as a power discharged by an exclusively human capability such as the will” (Schalow, 2022: 29), from which it follows that “this act of reciprocating, then, defines the first and foremost overture or primarily gesture of freedom” (Schalow, 2022: 30). It is evident where Heidegger, in Schalow’s reading, is going to aim when it comes to the ethical and practical side: “Human freedom now no longer means freedom as a property of man, but man as a possibility of freedom” (Heidegger, 2002: 94).

The second chapter (A New Leaping-Off Place for Ethical Inquiry, pp. 40-66) develops the peculiar proprietorial relation to Being that emerges from the belonging of Dasein to Being mentioned above. In the light of that overcoming of anthropocentrism inherent in the Kehre, which, as mentioned, Schalow interprets as “the vestiges of an ecological turn (if only in retrospect he may be considered a proto-ecologist)” (Schalow, 2022: 41), the author of the text wonders what role is now concretely due to the ‘subject’ of his discourse, answering with reference to the notions of stewardship or guardianship as diriment models to outline the practical guidelines of living. As we have seen, for Heidegger, in spite of Kantian ethics and its opposition between freedom and nature, it happens that “the presencing of nature reserves to animals their own potential for flourishing”, and that “it is the source of that flourishing, or what is ownmost or endemic to it, which turns the pendulum of his ethical inquiry in an ecological direction, namely, the allocation of a habitat (requisite for the livelihood of any animal)”. Switching to a Heideggerian lexicon, this means that, “ontologically speaking, the earth provides the grounding for any such habitats, and, indeed, in connection with our capacity for dwelling” (Schalow, 2022: 44). It is as a consequence of such dwelling that a more original ethics, which Schalow calls the “ethos of situated dwelling” (Schalow, 2022: 43) can finally develop and which the author addresses in relation to the possibility of a socio-biotic community and with reference to future generations. The mirroring of ethics and politics is the consequence of all this. In this sense, “the political must be addressed anew through the development of that site – in connection with the unconcealment of being – through which Dasein’s capacity to dwell first becomes apparent, namely, the ethos” (Schalow, 2022: 51). In this sense, “to do so is to allow the possibility of the ethos of dwelling to inform the political, rather than vice versa” (Schalow, 2022: 51). Through his analysis of the notion of measure and of the difference of readings of history between Heidegger and Marx, Schalow answers the question related to “how to rediscover the origin of praxis outside the self-contained sphere of human identity, […] that is, a form of pure (self-)presence” (Schalow, 2022: 59) through the proprietorial relation between being and man, with stewardship assuming the role of “the highest level of formality that is emblematic of specific instances for exercising care over beings, i.e., in our comportments in being-in-the-world” (Schalow, 2022: 60). The thesis proposed is therefore that of dwelling as a fundamental notion to justify our role on earth and consequently the political implication that derives from it. For Schalow, in short, “dwelling has the key perquisite for the enactment of any governance of the polis” (Schalow, 2022: 64), consistent with the Heideggerian statement that “mortals dwell in that they save the earth” (Heidegger, 1971a: 148). The determination of the new role of the politician can only pass through this constitutive bond of ours with the earth.

The third chapter (The Global Stage of Politics and the Return to the Earth, pp. 67-84) considers “the assimilation of the political to the ends of techno-capitalism”, which “unleashes the forces of machination on a global state, assimilating all human activities to the cycle of production and consumption” (Schalow, 2022: 67), showing how an appeal to Heidegger allows one to disengage from such a reading of the political. Through a comparison with the Heideggerian overcoming of the Marxist vision of history, Schalow comes to argue that “the phenomenological maxim ‘back to the things itself’ reverberates anew as a call to a ‘return to the earth’”, thus outlining “an eco-phenomenology, or alternatively, a phenomenology that speaks of a ‘return to the earth’”, which stands as “a form of attunement, an environmental ‘listening’ to nature and its diverse habitats” (Schalow, 2022: 68).

The fourth chapter (Temporality, Freedom, and Place, pp. 85-132) focuses on two crucial themes. On the one hand, the “deconstruction of modern politics as legitimizing the anthropocentric ends of domination, exploitation”, and, on the other, “the emergence of a trans-human perspective of freedom as a countermeasure to the assimilation of the political to the gestalt of machination” (Schalow, 2022: 86), both of which are necessary in view of the ecological turn mentioned above. As a consequence of Dasein’s peculiar relationship with freedom, already outlined in the first chapter, there is a shift of the axis of the political in a non-anthropocentric direction, in which governance must be built on the observation of our constitutive being-with-others. Schalow therefore identifies “three corollaries that comprise the ‘pillars of the polis,’ namely, the elements for its construction on a trans-human axis of dwelling” (Schalow, 2022: 87): the reciprocity of freedom (pp. 100-109), the people of future generations (pp. 109-118) and the epochal character of a measure (pp. 118-129). It is clear, however, that if “the polis brings to fruition, as a distinctive historical act, the challenge posed to man to fulfill the mandate of belonging to being and thereby build a political realm that is anchored in humanity’s capacity to dwell” (Schalow, 2022: 92), the reconfiguration of the political can only start from an analysis of this notion, central to delineating the dwelling and consequently a trans-human community. The thesis advanced is that leaving the technocratic rules prevailing today, the authentic notion of polis finds a new reconfiguration: “Being is not to be determined via the authoritarian rule of the polis”, but, on the contrary, it now means that “to re-establish the polis is to seek its origin in compliance with a new ‘measure’, which can counterbalance human and animal interests, the claim of future generations and the task of safeguarding the earth” (Schalow, 2022: 129). In this way, therefore, the polis manages to be anchored to human dwelling.

The fifth chapter (The Turn Toward Stewardship. Is a Socio-Biotic Community Possible?, pp. 133-184) extends what emerged in the previous chapter to a collective dimension, namely the possibility of belonging to a socio-biotic community, since “the stewardship by which we inhabit the earth calls into question the priorities of any (world-) citizenship, such that the development of a community (das Gemeinwesen) through the grounding of a site must be forged at the juncture between the human and the non-human” (Schalow, 2022: 134). With reference also to topical elements, such as the Covid-19 pandemic (p. 137) or the racial divisions in the U.S. (p. 147-150), Schalow focuses on that “further social-political dimension as the flipside to the responsiveness, the responsibility, by which mortals become answerable to or heed the voice of being” (Schalow, 2022: 137), a necessary consequence of that “counter resonance of the earth, nature, and animal life” (Schalow, 2022: 138) that has emerged since the first chapter. Schalow argues that “environmental practice is intrinsic to dwelling […] not as a value, but rather as an extension of freedom as ‘letting-be’” (Schalow, 2022: 150). What emerges is the thesis that “the task assigned to us through our dwelling” is to be “tenants of the earth” (Schalow, 2022: 161). Rewriting Protagoras’ famous statement for which “man is the measure of all things” (Plato, 1973: 17), the author argues that, “when divested of his anthropocentric focus, and thereby embracing his/her transience, ‘man’ become the ‘measure’ again”. It is enough not to lose sight of the fact that “Dasein is simultaneously ‘measured-by’ the proprietorship of ‘belonging to’ and thereby can ‘set the measure’ for any compliance and possible governance” (Schalow, 2022: 162) in that “poetic dwelling” that echoes Heidegger’s reading of Hölderlin (Heidegger, 1971b: 209-227). The notion of measure, recurring in several places in Schalow’s text and fundamental “to offset or counter the one-sidedness of human interests” (Schalow, 2022: 169), is essential to the conclusion reached by the author: “The socio-biotic community provides a setting in which human beings can ‘think globally, act locally’ (through their enactment of building, dwelling, thinking)”, with the proprietorship of dwelling that “restores limits, by granting space non-human dimensions of the earth to thrive and flourish” (Schalow, 2022: 166).

The call for a trans-human egalitarianism that flows from Heidegger’s overcoming of anthropocentrism is also the crux of the work’s conclusion, with Schalow arguing how, in light of the creation of that socio-biotic community that flows from our dwelling on earth, “a new kind of equality becomes possible as mortals protect the habitats of the diverse creatures that ‘co-habit’ the earth with us” (Schalow, 2022: 178). Once again, it is the notions of stewardship and dwelling that redefine our peculiar role on this planet: “The ‘to be’ of mortals as ‘tenants of the earth’ deepens the meaning of the ‘who’ of human beings as ‘world-citizens’” (Schalow, 2022: 178). The way of belonging to the earth that is proper to Dasein leads the author to think of a “new ‘egalitarianism’” with the role of “formal indicator of how we can characterize practices that prioritize environmental concerns over against the anthropocentric focus of modernity” (Schalow, 2022: 178). Thus, only in this way “a concern for the welfare of the earth and nature, humans and animals, can spark a conversation about the future of our historical sojourn and the fate of those generations still to come” (Schalow, 2022: 179). Through the five chapters of which the text is composed, we understand how the theses stated in the preface and introduction – above all, “the political must be housed in the eco-logical, that is, in the ‘eco’ or residence of dwelling” (Schalow, 2022: 3) – are confirmed through a careful reading of Heidegger’s work.

The overall result of Frank Schalow’s work can only be valued in a positive way. In an age in which Martin Heidegger’s thought seems to be more and more the exclusive prerogative of a type of literature aimed at illustrating his complicity with Nazism, this book certainly stands out for the original and proactive use that can still be made today of the complex Denkweg of the author of Sein und Zeit. Obviously, some questions remain open. In the first place, one could raise doubts about the legitimacy of basing, from a theoretical and methodological point of view, the guidelines of such a project on ontological justifications advanced by someone who, like Heidegger, is moved by theoretical interests apparently unrelated to similar intentions – in short, one might ask, “why refer to Heidegger?”. Similarly, as far as the moral side is concerned, we could question the opportunity, repeatedly highlighted by today’s detractors of his work, to make a figure such as Martin Heidegger, whose compromise with the Nazi regime went far beyond the convenience of the facade and career of many of his contemporaries, the ‘tutelary deity’ of an ethical project. On the other hand, however, Schalow makes no secret of his aim to propose an interpretation that from the beginning is subordinate to practical purposes; a rereading that intends to “reap tangible results” and “not to become merely an “academic’ exercise” (Schalow, 2022: 8). From this point of view, Heidegger’s Ecological Turn can be seen as a perfectly successful attempt.

Bibliography

Arendt, Hannah. 1992. Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Edited by Ronald Beiner. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Badiou, Alain; Cassin, Barbara. 2016. Heidegger. His Life & His Philosophy. Translated by Susan Spitzer. New York: Columbia University Press.

Di Cesare, Donatella. 2018. Heidegger and the Jews. The “Black Notebooks”. Translated by Murtha Baca. Cambridge-Medford: Polity Press.

Faye, Emmanuel. 2009. Heidegger. The Introduction of Nazism into Philosophy in Light of the Unpublished Seminars of 1933-1935. Translated by Michael B. Smith. New Haven-London: Yale University Press.

Farías, Victor. 1989. Heidegger and Nazism. Edited by Joseph Margolis and Tom Rockmore. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Heidegger, Martin. 1971a. “Building Dwelling Thinking”. Poetry, Language, Thought. Translated by Albert Hofstadter. New York: HarperCollins. pp. 141-159.

Heidegger, Martin. 1971b. “‘… Poetically Man Dwells…’”. Poetry, Language, Thought. Translated by Albert Hofstadter. New York: HarperCollins. pp. 209-227.

Heidegger, Martin. 1998. “Letter on ‘Humanism’”. Pathmarks. Edited by William McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 239-276.

Heidegger, Martin. 2002. The Essence of Human Freedom. An Introduction to Philosophy. Translated by Ted Sadler. London-New York: Continuum.

Plato. 1973. Theaetetus. Edited by John McDowell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Schalow, Frank. 2022. Heidegger’s Ecological Turn. Community and Practice for Future Generations. New York-London: Routledge.

Trawny, Peter; Mitchell, Andrew J. (Ed.) 2017. Heidegger’s “Black Notebooks”. Responses to Anti-Semitism. New York: Columbia University Press.

Thomas Rohkrämer: Martin Heidegger: Eine politische Biographie, Ferdinand Schöningh, 2020






Martin Heidegger: Eine politische Biographie Book Cover




Martin Heidegger: Eine politische Biographie





Thomas Rohkrämer





Ferdinand Schöningh




2020




Paperback




VIII + 297

Aaron James Wendland, Christopher Merwin, Christos Hadjioannou (Eds.): Heidegger on Technology






Heidegger on Technology Book Cover




Heidegger on Technology




Routledge Studies in Twentieth-Century Philosophy





Aaron James Wendland, Christopher Merwin, Christos Hadjioannou (Eds.)





Routledge




2018




Hardback £96.00




346

Reviewed by: Florian Arnold (Heidelberg University and State Academy of Fine Arts Stuttgart, Germany)

Releasing Gestell

Our daily life is influenced deeply and massively by technical devices, while their effects on our economic, social or even political behaviour are largely unknown. It seems obvious that we are not yet at the end of the story regarding technology but rather at the very beginning of an unforeseeable change, a downright revolution whose real import only the future will show. Given that technologies always had a crucial impact on human mindsets we have now entered a new realm of reality in terms of a global digitization. What determines this new era as truly new relates to intricate challenges on every field of human activity or thought, touching upon our very self-image as human beings. Can we still take for granted that we only change our equipment without, in turn, being equally changed by it? How can we cope with this new situation? And how can we develop a proper understanding of what is going on around us – or even with us?

In this state of affairs Heidegger’s reflections on technology and his equally famous and opaque notion “das Gestell” have gained renewed attention. For addressing our current situation on an “ontological”, or to be precise: a “seinsgeschichtlichen” level, his approach provides the reader with deeper “insights in that what is” than a mere description of surface phenomena. Philosophically speaking, we are dealing with a technical mode of unconcealing that not only transforms both our practical and theoretical encounters with a mostly concealed world. For in doing so it increases the same concealment to an extent such that we even forget about its very “nature” or “essence” (“Wesen”, or rather “Unwesen” in this case). According to this setting the expectations run high where a publication like the present “Heidegger on Technology” is concerned, which not only lays claim to clarifying Heidegger’s relation to technology but even engages in a broader discussion, following the editor’s appeal “to apply Heidegger’s analysis of technology to some of the most pressing ethical and political problems we confront today.” (8)

“Heidegger on Technology” contains instructive contributions that provide its readers with plenty of insights concerning Heidegger’s development of thought, whether it be its breaks or its continuities. Like any other companion it offers useful hints, much needed clarifications, even congenial interpretations; but also mere recapitulations of already prominent ideas. The book contains 17 articles, starting with a former presentation by Mark A. Wrathall, first given at the University of Sussex in 2016 which is representative for the inner tension between “Gestell” and “Gelassenheit” (“releasement”) both in the outline of the volume and of our time in general.

In The Task of Thinking in an Technological Age Wrathall argues for a reconfiguration of the academic curricula based on a late Heideggerian approach which abandons homogenisation, forgetfulness, and efficacy in favour of what Heidegger calls “thinking”. Wrathall advocates a certain “sensibility” (“Besinnung”, 31) towards contingency and whatever is questionable in our lifeworld, a kind of sense for possibilities and options that we are to choose for the purpose of an alternative way of life: “to accomplish Heidegger’s purposes, an education in history needs to highlight the discontinuities in style, and emphasize the breaks and ruptures between worlds which show those worlds to be lacking in determinate foundations.” (33)

It is worth mentioning, however, that Wrathall does not stop at this point. May teaching first be conceptualized as a close collaboration of learning subjects (which finds an echo in Iain Thomson’s article)[i], he hereafter goes deeper into a “apprenticeship in skilful behaviour” (34) by stating: “All of this suggests that an education in thinking requires a curriculum that includes fostering bodily skills, even if–especially if–those skills have no ready value in the global economy. For instance, the inclusion of sports in educational curricula […] should not be on training a few athletes to play a role in the entertainment industry”. (36) Should “releasement” from the Gestell finally lead to sports in terms of a “non-calculable” flow, representing “the surprising, the genuinely risky, the open-ended”? (36)

In fact there is some evidence that this is indeed a genuinely Heideggerian line of thought, considering his affections for the former German team leader Franz Beckenbauer but also his attempts during his rectorship to militarize the academic curriculum. The latter rather foils Wrathall intentions but at the same time it sheds some light on the inherent dialectics of this case: playfulness seems to be an essential condition of releasement but when it comes to a normative structuring for the purpose of social engagement, like in the case of an academic schedule, the Gestell comes nearer and, finally, the game could be over before it begins. In other words: Unless we are not willing to serve the Gestell, could Gelassenheit remain something else than an end in itself? For taken as a means, instead, we have been already caught in the trap of gamification, understood as the post-industrial revenge of the Gestell, instrumentalizing creativity, inspiration, flow etc. for its own ends. From this perspective the question whether there could be other ways to (re)interpret Heidegger’s notion of releasement, and what they should look like becomes crucial.

Bret W. Davis’ reading of the Country Path Conversations appears to offer such a way: Heidegger’s Realeasement From the Technological Will. In a well-informed recapitulation of Heidegger’s intellectual development since Being and Time Davis shows that the concept of the will plays a central role during all periods. For the will is already literally present in the “umwillen” of Dasein’s care-structure, and thus marks an episode directly leading into Heidegger’s commitment to National socialism.[ii] But it was only after Heidegger resigned from his rectorship and his deeper study of Hölderlin and Nietzsche that he saw clearer: his own existential voluntarism had in a way imitated the ‘will to will’, carried out to its devastating consequences in WWII especially by the Nazis but also by the Communists or even the ‘Americans’. According to this late insight Davis states a “second turn”: “Heidegger’s thought-path also underwent a ‘second turn’ around 1940, a turn from a tendency to think the relation between human being and being (beyng) in terms of will, and a turn to a sustained attempt to think this relation in terms of a non-willing releasement and letting-be.” (136) This willing, however, exhibits a well-known dialectic: the “willing to/of non-willing”, in order to be successful, requires a releasement from quasi any “to”. And while releasement “to” is not under the dictate of being or a result of our mute obedience, every releasement “to” remains a willing, even in the case of a “non-willing” and is therefore no proper releasement (We will come back to this point later).

Following the Country Path Conversations, Tobias Keiling compellingly demonstrates that only in respect to particular beings a ‘will to thinking’ in terms of generalising subsumptions can be overcome. In his radical reading of Heidegger’s “Seinsgeschichte” the notion of “being” itself tends to occupy the horizons of possible interpretations when it comes to singular beings. By presupposing that there is one final horizon of all horizons, we fail to recognize (the basic insight of set theory) that the plurality of things is accompanied by a plurality of ontologies (108), settled in a strictly open “horizon”, and, therefore, open to a transfinite series of encounters. We only get in touch with “things for themselves”, instead of “things in themselves”, or things for us, if we learn to let things be in such a way that we cease our ontological commitment (104). Releasement in this sense means letting, not even letting be – and thus enables, in turn, the freeing of thinking from its own will to think only for itself.  Correspondingly, one could say, released thinking is letting things be ends in themselves, and what is more: a thinking on behalf of things.

So far, so good. But does this apply only to a released thinking in Heidegger’s sense or also to a released thinking of the Gestell itself – a thinking that thinks on behalf of the Gestell by letting it be for itself? Looking for an answer, one of the first things that comes to mind could be the reply: Like science, the Gestell doesn’t think. But like in science, there is still a calculative intelligence at work, even if Heidegger is not willing to call it thinking. But then “was heißt denken”? Heidegger’s general answer amounts to letting beings be as well as thinking led by being. Now, Technology is a mode of disclosure, and the Gestell is the very “Wesen” of technology, a “Wesen” of being, thus even if the Gestell itself does not think, it lets think for itself by leading our thoughts (into itself). So, the question arises: Must we distinguish a ‘good’ from a ‘bad’ thinking – as two modes of being’s disclosure?

In fact it is not Gelassenheit whose opponent is the Gestell, but the “Geviert”. And so releasement turns out to be a mere vehicle of transition on the way from Gestell to Geviert. According to this characteristic of Gelassenheit, as a vehicle or device, it shows striking resemblance to Husserl’s epoché, understood as the enabling condition of a phenomo-logic. As Christos Hadjioannou reconstructs in his text Heidegger’s Critique of Techno-science as a Critique of Husserl’s Reductive Method Heidegger’s early notion of a “formal indication” lays ground to his critique of a so-called “care about certainty” (66) in Husserl’s concept of phenomenology as transcendental science: “So, formal indication lets everything stand as is, without referring, without imposing on things any pre-judged order. By indicating phenomena, it unassumingly releases them into the open, allowing them to show themselves from themselves. Thus, with ‘formal indication’, Heidegger attempts to replace Husserlian phenomenological analysis with a hermeneutic praxis that does not objectify, that does not posit any sort of order or classification, that does not assume an indifferent stance towards the content of phenomena, hiding the enactmental character of the philosophical praxis, and that does not slip into an attitudinal/theoretical comportment.” (71)

Sounds familiar. But here we see now that Heidegger, right from the beginning, is engaged in the methodological question of how to let things be, in order to let them show themselves. “Hermeneutical praxis” in this sense shall overcome “phenomenological analysis” by giving things a voice in the conversation of being, whereas Husserlian phenomenology seems to objectify things by quasi scrutinizing them only in respect of its own ‘worldview’. In other words: Heidegger’s methodological ground (or unground) is language, rather than the supposed ocularcentrism of Husserlian phenomenology. Therefore, Heidegger’s own philosophical praxis approaches poetry. Until this reversement from scientific classifications to the inner heart of the named holy, the Geviert, is executed, there will be no releasement from the Gestell according to Heidegger.

A deeper discussion of this relation is found in Susanne Claxton’s Poetry and the Gods. From Gestell to Gelassenheit, and here again, the emphasis lies on Gelassenheit. While not being wrong, this constitutes only one half of the way towards Heiddegger’s language as a phenomenology of poetry. As Claxton herself knows, Heidegger’s evoking of gods, the mortals, sky, and earth within the Geviert is not metaphorical in a pejorative sense. Instead, he truly believes in gods that rise to speak through their prayer-like addressing by mortals. As Claxton puts it: “For myths are not explanations, but rather ways of creatively conceptualizing experiences, experiences felt and perceived by mortals to be encounters with something outside themselves, something that has force.” (238) And later: “A given god, as such, can feel nothing in himself; the god needs a mortal to feel for him. Understood in this way, divinities may be seen as affective powers intending toward manifestations via mortals as embodied expressions thus experienced. In the coming together of mortal and divinity, fullness of experience is achieved.” (239) In other words: What is to be saved from the Gestell are certain extraordinary “feelings” (“Stimmungen”) that are conveyed, articulated, and experienced through a quasi-divine poetical language. These “Stimmungen” need “Stimmen” (“voices”) in order to not be ignored and forgotten. And so, it is not only for the sake of the gods that “Dasein” shall listen attentively to what ‘his’ experiences tell him.

Yet as we have already heard, gods are not the only ones who “need” or “use” (“brauchen”) Dasein as a kind of resonator. Moreover, the question seems to be whether gods simply do not feel or whether they do not think either. If the latter, there could very well be other gods than the mythological ones – for instance, technical ones or what we tend to call artificial intelligences. Without going too much into detail here, it seems quite obvious that they (still) need and are (already) using (“brauchen”) us, as well. Whereas the Geviert, in Heidegger’s view, stands for the holy shrine of the mystery (“Geheimnis”), the Gestell could turn out to be the secular shrine of the “need of needlessness” (“Not der Notlosigkeit”)[iii]. To put it another way: Are we still in need (and use) of Heidegger’s gods? – I’m not sure. Maybe in need and use of others? But why call them gods any longer?

Moving on from the gods some of the contributions to the volume rightly stress the point that there is still a lot to concerning big issues of our time such as the need for a new ecology (Michael E. Zimmerman and Trish Glazebrook) or the outcomes of an “audit society” (Denis McManus). In all the three cases Heidegger’s notion of the Gestell (or its forerunner “Machenschaft”) functions like a guideline to conceptualize what is going wrong, even if there might be no complot or genius malignus behind the scenes. Especially in the case of the audit society we are facing developments that foil the intended results: “So despite audit’s ‘promise of accountability and visibility’ (Power 1997, 127)[iv], there is reason to think it makes it significantly harder to see where power actually lies.” (277) If we cede our powers of decision to anonymous evaluation systems or even algorithms we get lost in our own lifeworld when it comes to human politics.

To be clear on this point, I do not deny that it is crucial to engage in such critiques as supported by Heidegger’s conceptual framework. Releasement is fine and I acknowledge the policy of emphasizing this notion in place of the Geviert. Yet I side with McManus here when he asks at the end of his chapter: “even if we accept that Heidegger’s diagnosis of our contemporary situation sheds light on the phenomena that Power describes, is it the best diagnosis?” I think it is one of the best, and two out of four names which McManus mentions subsequently even based their own diagnosis on Heidegger’s (Foucault and Arendt, while Marx and Weber undergo Heidegger’s critique). The only question I am asking here is, how far one can get, sticking to Heidegger original attempt. Of course, there are still points to be made, for instance, against Habermas, when Julian Young points out that a Habermasian communicative rationality ignores a certain “need for dwelling” (205 et passim). Or when Aaron James Wendland shows that the Kuhnian concept of “paradigm shifts” still emphasizes assimilation tendencies after the break where Heidegger rightly sees a needful release (297). And even when Taylor Carman, regarding the controversy between Heidegger and Heisenberg, argues that ‘science still doesn’t think’ because of its reductionist concept of “physis” (309 et passim). But does this lead to Heidegger’s final insight that only a god can save us–a god of poetry and a poetry of gods?

I am afraid it does, but only if we accept that Hölderlin is the greatest poet and that dwelling means to ensconce oneself in Heidegger’s ‘house of being’, viz. in his private language of thinking under the advice of being, including his idiosyncrasies, wrong etymologies, and ‘mystery’ lecture performances. Then we might believe that we live in times of the “Not der Notlosigkeit” in an era of a self-accomplishing forgetfulness of being, of self-deceit, which manages to ignore its own need to be saved. And even today there are still several believers among Heidegger’s readers. But maybe (according to Heidegger’s late reticence) there will be no saving needed anymore. Not because everything is just fine, but because the Gestell, along with its essence, the “danger” (“Gefahr”), could be in itself already the saving (“Rettung”)–not the saving from it, but the saving for itself. In other words: Could there be a saving of the Gestell by letting it be (for itself)? Having said this, what would this actually mean?

There is one moment in his Bremen Lectures where Heidegger comes close to this point: “Das Wesen der Technik ist das Seyn selber in der Wesensgestalt des Ge-Stells. Das Wesen des Ge-Stells aber ist die Gefahr. […] Die Gefahr ist das Ge-Stell nicht als Technik, sondern als das Seyn. Das Wesende der Gefahr ist das Seyn selbst, insofern es der Wahrheit seines Wesens mit der Vergesslichkeit dieses Wesens nachstellt.“ (GA 79, 62)

Can being be forgotten, or even forget itself? In this passage Heidegger reflects on the essence not only of the Gestell and on what is meant to be the Gefahr, but also on the essence (or ‘the essenceing’ = “das Wesende”) of the Gefahr: “das Seyn” being after itself (“nachstellen”), and in so doing, disguising (‘verstellen’) itself with the “Ge-Stell”. Hence, the danger is, according to Heidegger, that there seems to be no danger. Like the “need of needlessness”, Heidegger conceives of a danger of “safety” (“Gefahrlosigkeit”, literally ‘dangerlessness’). According to its own dialectics, the essence of danger is un-essence (“Unwesen”), an essence (“Wesen”) that denies itself and in doing so finally would become the ‘essencelessness’ (= “Wesenlosigkeit”) of being, if it is not recalled by Dasein anymore as the danger of being or the threat of its own forgetfulness.

To let the Gestell be for itself would therefore mean not to ignore the danger of forgetting, but to recognize the danger of forgetting as that what it truly is: our fear of death, angst. The real danger seems to be that not even danger will remain when we are gone. But that is probably going to happen. In contrast, the inherent ‘nihilism’ of the Gestell reminds us not of death, but of the forgetfulness of death (expressed through the loss of angst). As a result, the threat to Heidegger’s own thinking, as a permeant contemplation of the meaning of death, is simply that it could be pointless–because of the meaninglessness of death. This, in turn, doesn’t mean that there is no being and yet it means that the meaning of being is not necessarily the being of meaning, or what Heidegger would call the “Ereignis” of meaningfulness.

To conclude I return to the Country Path Conversations and listen to what Steven Crowell has to say about the correlation between “Sein” and “Dasein” in his chapter: The Challenge of Heidegger’s Approach to Technology. A Phenomenological Reading: “The first thing to note is that Heidegger’s attempt to overcome representational thinking does not abandon correlationism […]. Heidegger is quite clear about this: ‘das Seyn braucht den Menschen’ (GA 65: 261), the worlding of world requires the thinking being (GA 77: 147). But one might wonder whether Heidegger’s late notion of thinking as the ‘indwelling releasement to the worlding of world’ retains the feature of the care-structure that […] is the phenomenological ground of meaning–namely, trying to be (Worumwillen). Is the ‘relation to the essence of the human being’ that allows the Open ‘to be as it is [wesen…wie es west]’ (GA 77: 146), a relation that involves my being at issue in trying to be a thinker?” (89)

In the last sentence before this passage Crowell added an endnote. In this endnote Crowell replies to Quentin Meillassoux in defence of Heidegger’s correlationism: “Calling something an arche-fossil or a hammer or an electron–or a jug or a Gegnet or a Geviert, for that matter–has a determinate meaning only in a normative context grounded in the speaker’s commitment. The ‘realism’ which opposes this is perfectly suited to Ge-stell since, by denying the correlational conditions of meaning, it does away with meaning altogether and bottoms out in nihilism.” (94)

This punchline is remarkable, not primarily, however, as a critique but rather in the sense that Crowell laudably clarifies the relation (or correlation?) between a so-called “speculative realism” (or in the case of Meillassoux: speculative materialism) and the prevailing Gestell. Indeed, we are living in the Gestell, and Meillassoux somehow approves this insight by transcending every correlationism stemming from an anthropocentric vision of thinking. Now, is there a contradiction implied in what Crowell refers to? So far as I can see, none that Meillassoux hasn’t already dealt with elsewhere. Instead, there are consequences that concern not least the Heideggerian concept of releasement. Whereas Heidegger tries to free thought from the Gestell in order to gain a free relation to technology, speculative realism takes the opposite view: the freeing of thought from “Dasein”.

There still might be “the correlational conditions of meaning” but only for us as a species which cannot cease to make sense of everything, even nothing. But unfortunately that does not guarantee that beyond human comprehension meaning exists at all. Instead, we are today facing a situation wherein an intelligent form of calculation takes command without any proper understanding of its own agenda. And the same holds for philosophical speculations on the necessity of contingency, necessitating us to think the end of thinking as a possible, although unthinkable event (or rather “Enteignis”). Therefore, to talk about releasement under present conditions points, if anything, to a releasement into “nihilism” – according to our human, all-to-human presuppositions and expectations. Even though this does not mean that meaning does not mean anything to us, we find ourselves alone, surrounded by silicon and silence.

The German term “Gelassenheit” has its Latin equivalent in the Christian notion of “resignatio”. What in English still echoes the expression “resignation” or “resign” is translated into German as “Entlassung” – another, often unmentioned morphological derivation of “lassen”. Could it be that Heidegger’s own “releasement” from onto-theo-technology only renamed his resigning, his resignation by the Gestell, seine Entlassung durch die Seinsgeschichte? In this case he would have been the first and last thinker of the complete “Enteignis”: ‘The end of philosophy and the task/capitulation (“Aufgabe”) of thinking’ within the Gestell…a releasement from a self-annihilating being (“Sein”), and into a new substantial commitment with beings (“Seienden”)…the reversal from resigning to designing?


[i]See Technology, Ontotheology, Education, p. 185: “At the heart of Heidegger’s reontologization of education is a rethinking of what is called ‘learning,’ in which teaching itself becomes ‘the highest form of learning,’ an exemplary art of ‘learning-in-public,’ from which students learn how to learn by example, and learning comes to stand higher than being learned or knowing. (In what I have called ‘the pedagogical truth event,’ teachers learn to come into their own as teachers by showing students how to disclose the being of entities creatively, responsively, and responsibly, thereby helping students, things, and being all come into their own together.)” This “pedagogical truth event”, as Thomson calls it, seems to be already a common praxis, especially in demographic societies where youthfulness represents a rare good, whereas maturity is believed to be a kind of sale out.

[ii]For a closer reading of Heidegger’s thinking having an affair with National Socialism see Aaron James Wendland contribution to the present volume: Heidegger’s New Beginning. History, Technology, and National Socialism.

[iii]The German expression “Not” has also the connotation of “misery”.

[iv]McManus is quoting the inventor of the term “Audit Society” Michael Power in his book: The Audit Society: Rituals of Verification, Oxford: Oxford University Press 1997.

Aaron James Wendland, Christopher Merwin, Christos Hadjioannou (Eds.): Heidegger on Technology, Routledge, 2018






Heidegger on Technology Book Cover




Heidegger on Technology




Routledge Studies in Twentieth-Century Philosophy





Aaron James Wendland, Christopher Merwin, Christos Hadjioannou (Eds.)





Routledge




2018




Hardback £120.00




346

Antonio Cerella, Louiza Odysseos (Eds.): Heidegger and the Global Age, Rowman & Littlefield International, 2017






Heidegger and the Global Age Book Cover




Heidegger and the Global Age




New Heidegger Research





Antonio Cerella, Louiza Odysseos (Eds.)





Rowman & Littlefield International




2017




Hardback £90.00




338